|
A duty is a moral obligation that an agent has towards another
person, such as the duty not to lie. Etymologically, duties are
actions that are due to someone else, such as paying money that
one owes to a creditor. In a broader sense, duties are simply actions
that are morally manditory. Medieval philosophers such as Aquinas
argued that we have specific duties or obligations to avoid committing
specific sins. Since sins such as theft are absolute, then our duty to
avoid stealing is also absolute, irrespective of any good consequences
that might arise from particular acts of theft. From the 17th to the 19th
centuries, many philosophers held the normative theory that moral conduct
is that which follows a specific list of duties. These theories are also
called deontological theories, from the Greek word deon, or
duty, since they emphasize foundational duties or obligations. We find one
of the first clear indications of this view in The Law of War and
Peace (1625) by Dutch philosopher Hugo Grotius (1583-1645). For
Grotius, our ultimate duties are fixed features of the universe, which
even God cannot change, and comprise the chief obligations of natural law.
Some moral theorists at the time based their list of duties on traditional
lists of virtues.
Table of Contents (Clicking on the links below will take you to that part of this article)
In On the Law of Nature and of Nations (1672), German philosopher Samual Pufendorf (1632-1694) refined three particular components of duty theory. First, Pufendorf adopts a position that scholars now call "the correlativity of rights and duties." On this view, every right that I have implies a duty on your part to respect my right. For example, if I have a right to own my car, then you have a duty not to steal my car. From a moral standpoint, Pufendorf believed that duties were more important than rights. Second, Pufendorf distinguished between perfect and imperfect duties. Perfect duties are obligations that are precisely defined, and dictate our proper conduct everywhere at all times, such as the duty not to steal. Imperfect duties, by contrast, such as the duty to be charitable, are not fixed, but open as to when and how we perform this duty. Third, Pufendorf provided a detailed categorization of all duties into three main groups: duties to God, duties to oneself, and duties to others. In the selection below, from The Duty of Man and Citizen (1673), Pufendorf argues that duties to others are the most foundational of the three, since this most immediately follows the mandate of natural law that we are to be sociable. Concerning our duties towards God, he argues that there are two kinds: (1) a theoretical duty to know the existence and nature of God, and (2) a practical duty to both inwardly and outwardly worship God. Concerning our duties towards oneself, these are also of two sorts: (1) duties of the soul, which involve developing one's skills and talents, and (2) duties of the body, which involve not harming our bodies such as through gluttony or drunkenness, and not killing oneself. Concerning our duties towards others, Pufendorf divides these between absolute duties, which are universally binding on people, and conditional duties, which are the result of contracts between people. Absolute duties are of three sorts: (1) avoid wronging others; (2) treat people as equals, and (3) promote the good of others. Conditional duties are far reaching and involve every aspect of social contracts and agreements. The first of these is to keep one's promises.
Pufendorf's division of moral duties quickly became a standard tool among moral theoriests for determining moral conduct. For example, Hume opens his essay "On Suicide" with the statement that "If suicide be criminal, it must be a transgression of our duty either to God, our neighbour, or ourselves." German philosophers, such as Christian Wolff (1679-1754) and Alexander Gottleib Baumgarten (1714-1762), followed Pufendorf's key distinctions. Philosophers at this time also distinguished between direct duties and indirect duties. For example, I have a direct duty to show you respect, since you are immediately entitled to respect. By contrast, I have only an indirect duty to be respectful to the bodies of dead people; the dead person himself has no immediate entitlement to respect, but acting disrespectfully towards a corpse will negatively impact the living relatives of the dead person.
Problems with Traditional Duty Theory. One problem
with traditional duty-based ethics involves the list of prescribed
duties. What was self-evident in the 17th and 18th centuries seems less
self-evident
today. The existence and nature of God are more widely questioned now,
hence it is speculation to claim that we have a set of duties toward God.
Advocates of personal liberty question the traditional duties to
ourselves. For example, the right to suicide is now widely defended, and
the right to self-rule implies that I can let my faculties and abilities
deteriorate if I so choose. Finally, many of the traditional duties to
others have also been under fire. Defenders of personal liberty question
our duties of benevolence, such as charity, and political duties, such as
public spirit. For some, the traditional list of self-evident duties needs
to be reduced to one: the duty to not harm others.
Another problem with traditional duty theory is that there
is no clear procedure for resolving conflicts between duties. Suppose I am
placed in a situation where I must choose between feeding myself to avoid
starvation, or feeding my neighbor to keep her from starving.
Consequentialist theories provide a clear formula for resolving this
conflict: the morally correct choice is the one which produces the
greatest benefit (either to myself, or to society at large). Traditional
duty theory, by contrast, does not offer a procedure for determining
which obligation is primary. Without such a procedure, it is inadequate in
its present form.