Notes on the Problem of Evil
Sandra LaFave
Philosopher J. L. Mackie published “Evil and Omnipotence” in 1955. That article has become a classic philosophical statement of the problem of evil. Mackie’s article is online here, and it serves as the broad outline for these notes. Mackie was not the first philosopher to address the problem of evil, however. The problem is entrenched in the history of philosophy and theology. Attempts to solve it even have a special name: theodicies. Omnipotence Let’s get clear (if we can) on the concept of omnipotence first.
From Latin, “omni-” means “all”; “potentia” means “power”. So an omnipotent being has all powers.
An omnipotent being can do anything.
But believers have been trying to figure it out,
without much success, for centuries, what omnipotence really means.
For example, can God create a stone he can’t lift?
(If he can, he’s not omnipotent because he can’t lift it;
if he can’t, he’s not omnipotent, because he can’t create it.)
Can God violate the laws of logic? If God can do anything, can God make 2+2 equal 5?
Can God decide to become supremely evil? Can God commit suicide?
You can see the problems here, no?
It looks like unlimited omnipotence leads to contradictions.
“Omnipotence” might mean
Unlimited Omnipotence:
God can do anything at all that anyone can think of. Some theologians think this.
Qualified Omnipotence:
God can do whatever he chooses to do, but his choices are limited because
God imposes limits on himself. For example: many theists say God (as Creator)
first created logic and the rules of nature and then chose to follow
the rules of logic and also chose not to interfere in the operation of the laws of nature. God created humans with free will
and chooses not to interfere with that.
AND/OR
The nature of God doesn’t allow him to do some
things. For example, since God is essentially good, he can’t
become bad.
Qualified omnipotence is the more common view among theologians than unlimited omnipotence. This is because
the God of Christianity
is a logos-type God, unlike the Old Testament God or the gods of the ancient Greek and Roman pantheon.
Those gods were unpredictable, irrational, unjust, and vindictive.
If you were unlucky enough to incur the wrath of one of those gods,
you were doomed to eternal suffering, even if you were a virtuous person.
The logos God of the New Testament, by contrast, follows the rules of logic,
and is thereby constrained.
The universe is consistent (i.e., it follows rules, enabling it to be known
by science) and the universe is ultimately morally fair:
good is rewarded and evil is punished.
What is the problem of evil? You’ve probably heard of the problem of evil (also known
as the problem of suffering): if God loves us, as Christians say, and he is just and fair and all-knowing
and omnipotent, then why is human life often so
full of suffering? The suffering of innocent people, e.g., children, seems especially cruel.
The God of Christianity knows that innocent children suffer. He's omnipotent, which means
he could make the suffering go away. And he's supposedly a loving God (a loving father, according
to popular imagery); what kind of loving father would allow his child to starve to death or
die from some horrible disease? Some people, like J. L. Mackie, view the problem of evil as
the most powerful argument
for atheism. A famous literary statement of the problem of evil can be found in Feodor Dostoevsky's famous novel
The Brothers Karamazov.
In Confessions, Chapter 5, Augustine states the problem: “Whence is evil?
Or was there some evil matter of which He made and formed and ordered it,
but left something in it which He did not convert into good? But why was this?
Was He powerless to change the whole lump, so that no evil should remain in it,
seeing that He is omnipotent? Lastly, why would He make anything at all of it,
and not rather by the same omnipotency cause it not to be at all?”
Mackie puts it this way:
the following three statements comprise an
inconsistent set: they cannot all be simultaneously
true:
God is omnipotent (meaning there are no limits
to what God can do).
God is all-good (good in the sense of being actively opposed to evil).
Evil exists.
According to Mackie, one of these statements must be false.
Another common way to state the atheist argument that arises from the problem of
evil and omnipotence is a reductio ad absurdum (indirect) proof.
This version claims that absurd (i.e., contradictory) consequences
follow from the supposition that there is an omnipotent and totally good God.
Hence, that supposition cannot be true.
If the supposition cannot be true, no such God can exist. Here's the indirect proof: To prove: There is no God (“God” meaning a being who is
both omnipotent and totally good). Suppose:
There is such a God. (I.e., suppose the opposite of the claim we want to
prove.) If
there is such a God and he’s omnipotent, then there are no limits to what
he can do. That’s what “omnipotent” means. If
there is such a God and he’s good, he’d tend to make evil go away. Or, if there is a totally good being,
he at minimum doesn’t make things worse; he improves things. Evil
and suffering are bad. If
evil and suffering exist, things could be better.
Evil and suffering exist. So
things could be better. But
if there is a God who is really omnipotent and totally good, then there
should be no evil or suffering. God is powerful enough to eliminate it
altogether, and he’s totally good, so he should (as a matter of
definition) eliminate it altogether. If there is a God who’s omnipotent
and totally good, in other words, things really couldn’t be better! There
is a contradiction between statements 7 and 8. The contradiction
follows directly from the supposition in
statement 1. Therefore statement 1
is absurd. Q.E.D. As I have presented the argument, it may sound dry. But it carries a lot of emotional
weight. Many people struggle with
suffering – health problems, war, famine, losses of all kinds. Religious people often tell sufferers to
have faith that God will take their suffering away. But I think sufferers want to know why they’re suffering
to begin with. If God could have eliminated suffering, and he didn’t,
then why didn’t he? And if he didn’t eliminate suffering, how can he be
called good at all (let alone totally good); he seems to be just a
sadist. This is a hard problem for believers as well as unbelievers; religious
bookstores frequently have titles such as “Why Does God Let Bad Things Happen
to Good People?” or “Why Did You Do This to Me, God?”.
Some people say the cause of evil is Satan, or the devil.
Philosophers don’t usually consider this explanation as separate from the classic problem of
evil because it seems to be the same problem in another form:
"Why doesn’t God just get rid of Satan once and for all?
If he’s omnipotent, he can.
If he’s omnibenevolent, he wants to.
So why doesn’t he?"
Philosophical and theological responses to this are the same as for the classic problem of evil.
Solutions that Work (the unorthodox ones, according to Mackie) Now, you can make the problem of evil go away, but
you have to deny key elements of Christian doctrine. In other words, the genuine solutions are unorthodox.
“Orthodox” is an interesting words.
Many of you know the word “orthodontia” because you’ve had your teeth
straightened. The “ortho” in
“orthodontia” means “straight” or “going the right way.” The “ortho” in “orthodox” also means
“straight” or “going the right way.” If
your opinions (doxa) are orthodox, they are along the right
lines; they are on the straight path and will not lead you astray. Many
Christian sects enforce doctrinal orthodoxy; that is, in order to be a member
in good standing, you must profess belief in certain articles of faith, and if
you don’t profess belief, you can’t be a member of the church in good standing
(you become a heretic or an apostate).
Among these articles of faith – or presupposed by them – are the claims
that God is totally good, God is omnipotent, and evil is real. There’s no
problem of evil if you’re willing to deny any of these claims.
“God
is not omnipotent” solves the problem.
Evil and suffering are no longer problems; God would like to
make them go away, and he would if he could, (‘cuz he’s good), but he’s
just not powerful enough.1
“God
is not totally good” solves the problem. Evil and suffering are now
perfectly understandable. Maybe they happen because God is cruel and mean -- quite a different conception of God.
“Evil
and suffering don’t exist” solves the problem.
There are two common versions of "evil doesn't exist": evil as privation of goodness (Augustine), or
evil as illusory (non-Western religions such as Hinduism and Buddhism).
Let's talk about these genuine but (alas) unorthodox solutions.
Genuine but unothodox Solution 1: "God is not omnipotent"
Now we need to recall the two notions of omnipotence described above, because the definition of "omnipotence" makes a difference in the degree of unorthodoxy this solution carries. There were two notions of omnipotence: unlimited omnipotence and qualified omnipotence. So denying omnipotence, then, (saying “God is not omnipotent”) might mean either
Unlimited omnipotence is false.
OR
Qualified omnipotence is false.
If unlimited omnipotence is false, God just tells the sufferer, “I'd sure like to relieve your suffering because you are my child and I love you, but I can’t do anything about it, sorry, never could.”
Denying qualified omnipotence is more complicated, though. The view that God's omnipotence is qualified is commonly-held, and orthodox,
even if not entirely intelligible.2
If “God is not omnipotent” means only
option (2) -- that divine omnipotence is qualified -- then we are still arguably orthodox.
If “God is not omnipotent” means “God chose to limit his powers,” then when the sufferer asks, "Why don't you do something about my suffering, God?",
God’s answer isn’t simply “Sorry, I can’t.”
It’s something like “Sorry about that. I’m can't make your suffering go away,
because I choose (or chose) not to interfere in the universe.”
God's answer now leads the sufferer to ask: “OK, why do you choose not to interfere?” and God might have perfectly good reasons for his choice.
We may have made some progress. Qualified omnipotence might be half of a solution to
the problem of evil.
The other half would have to be a reasonable answer to the sufferer’s question “Why don’t you help?”
Possible answers from God include:
“I couldn’t create good without evil.” “Logic made me do it,” “I allow evil because the universe is really better with suffering than without,” “I allow it because you caused it by your sins.”
These are the four so-called orthodox solutions to the problem of evil.
If any of these responses makes sense, the Christian can say "God chose not to
intervene, and I totally understand why."
Mackie, however, says all four of these orthodox solutions fail (more on this below).
Genuine but unorthodox Solution 2: "God isn't totally good"
Note that Mackie defines "totally good" as "actively opposed to evil", so that a totally good being
eliminates evil as far as it can. If we limit omnipotence in the way just described -- if we say, for example,
that God chooses to allow
natural evils (floods, earthquakes, disease, etc.) as part of the ordinary course of nature and
also chooses not to interfere in the exercise of human free will -- then
God is not totally good according to Mackie's definition. And remember, limited omnipotence is orthodox.
Thus if we could demonstrate that God's
choice to limit his own powers was reasonable (intelligible and logically consistent), then
we might be able to live with the notion that God isn't totally good in the way Mackie describes; i.e., God has
his reasons for choosing not to eliminate evil as much as he can.
Genuine but unorthodox Solution 3: "Evil doesn't exist"
Two common versions of "Evil doesn't exist" include
evil as privation (absence) of goodness, and evil as an illusion of unenlightened mind.
Evil as Privation
According to Augustine’s “evil as privation” view,
evil is essentially non-being.
Augustine says “For God, evil does not exist at all.”
Evil is the absence of good; it isn’t anything that is.
According to “evil as privation of good”
since evil doesn’t exist, we can’t experience evil.
We experience not pain, but “absence of comfort”.
We experience not sadness but “absence of happiness”.
We experience not disease but “absence of health”.
Augustine’s view is often said to “preserve omnipotence” in the
following way:
if evil doesn’t exist, as Augustine argues, the question of whether God is powerful
enough to eliminate it simply doesn’t arise, since there’s nothing to eliminate.
Augustine is a Church Father. As far as I can determine, the “evil as privation” view is orthodox.
Philosophers and theologians often note two kinds of evils:
Natural evils, such as death, disease, earthquakes, floods, and other natural disasters;
AND
Moral evils such as sins and dispositions to evil (bad character). Aquinas calls natural evils “evils of penalty” and moral evils “evils of fault”.
On the “evil as privation” view,
Natural evils result from God’s perfect creation
(perfect because the perfection of creation requires a hierarchy of goodness,
e.g., some stars are brighter, some animals more fierce, etc. ).
AND
Moral evils result from humans’ freely turning away from the greater good and choosing “lesser goods”.
In creating the universe with hierarchies of goodness, God is
clearly responsible for natural evils, but he can’t be said to have created them.
He allows them because all humans are sinful and deserve to suffer (Augustine);
or he allows them as consequences of the laws of nature operating normally (Aquinas)
because the universe is more perfect that way (more on this later).
Moral evils, on the other hand, are never caused by God and God is never responsible for them.
In either case, evil is simply absence of good or lesser good. It is non-being.
Evil as an Illusion of Unenlightened Mind
Non-Western religions such as Buddhism and Hinduism view evil as an illusion that
results from an unenlightened mind.
According to “evil as illusion,” suffering is caused by our thoughts. “I suffer” is just a story
I tell myself, but what I actually experience are just some sensations.
I wouldn’t experience them as suffering if I were fully enlightened.
According to non-Western religions,
if you think something is bad, that’s your ego projecting itself pridefully out at the universe.
But if you are enlightened, you realize that there’s nothing especially alarming about the cancer;
it just is, like everything else, and everything is always changing. The divine nature is
in the cancer as much as it’s in you, and besides, there’s really no “you” anyway.
Hence the problem of evil arises in Western religions only.
It seems to me that orthodox solution 3 – “Evil doesn’t exist” -- in either form is simply
not helpful to ordinary people as a solution to the problem of evil.
You say “Why did you do this to me, God?”
God says “Sorry you feel that way, but your cancer is just the absence of healthy cells.
Your pain is just the absence of comfort.”
It’s reasonable for the sufferer to feel frustrated by God’s answer, no?
The sufferer says to God “Well, maybe that works for you, but I can’t seem to define away the
cancer or the pain!
I’m still suffering here.”
To sum up so far, Mackie says "God is not omnipotent", "God is not totally good",
and "Evil does not exist" are genuine but unorthodox solutions to the problem of evil.
That is, a person who believes one or more of these views would not be welcome in most Christian faith communities.
But the situation is more complicated, I think. "God is not omnipotent" might just mean God has
chosen to limit his powers, and that view is orthodox. If we accept "God is not omnipotent" in that sense,
God is of course not "totally good" in Mackie's sense; i.e., God chooses not to eliminate evil as much as he
can. So we might have an orthodox solution to the problem of evil if we
can devise some intelligible and logically consistent rationale for God's choice to limit his powers.
Mackie says there is no such rationale. Let's see if Mackie is right.
Solutions that Don’t Work (the “orthodox” ones) According to Mackie, the usual “orthodox” solutions you
hear in churches are actually not orthodox at all. They actually presuppose one or more of the unorthodox solutions
described in the previous section. Thus, according to Mackie, there are no
orthodox solutions to the problem of evil. Mackie discusses four so-called “orthodox” solutions:
Evil
is necessary as a means to good; God could not create good without simultaneously bringing evil into existence.
Evil
is necessary as a logical counterpart to good.
The
universe is actually better with some evil in it than it would be if there
were none, since evil gives us the opportunity to grow and develop morally
and spiritually as a result of our confronting it in faith.
Evil
is due to human free will. You see this “solution” in the movie Oh, God. A child asks God (George Burns) why he
created the world with evil and suffering. God answers, “Can you tell me
another way I could have done it?” Sometimes believers use the analogy of a
mountain and a valley: they say, “You can’t make a mountain without
simultaneously making a valley. And in
the same way, God can’t create good things without simultaneously bringing bad
things into existence as a necessary consequence.”
Mackie replies: But most Christians believe God is not subject
to the ordinary causal laws of nature.
For example, God as Creator can create things out of nothing.
Why can’t an omnipotent God create a mountain without creating a valley?
According to Mackie, orthodox solution 1 masks unorthodox solution 1.
You can’t really say “God couldn’t have done it any other way” without denying omnipotence.
As we saw above, believers often say, “God chose not to be omnipotent. So God’s supposed inability to create a mountain without a valley is just the result of a constraint he put on himself.” Believers who say this have now qualified the notion of omnipotence.
But qualified omnipotence is less convincing here because
God as Creator is supposedly the author of causal laws.
God made the law requiring valleys with mountains.
That was his idea, and he presumably he could have done things a different way.
Maybe he did, in other universes.
Maybe we can’t think of a way to make a mountain without a valley, but we’re not omnipotent.
Mackie says, this so-called “solution”
really presupposes unorthodox solution #1: it presupposes that God is not
really omnipotent after all – an unorthodox view. “Orthodox” solution #1 is
really unorthodox solution #1.
Unsatisfactory “orthodox” solution 2: “Evil is necessary as a counterpart”
First we need to understand what this “solution” means.
According to Mackie, this means evil must necessarily exist if good exists,
since God is bound by the laws of logic, and “good” and “evil” are logical opposites.
Since “non-good” means evil, evil must exist if good exists.
Mackie makes two separate (and correct) logical points:
There are two different logical senses of “counterpart” or “opposite”:
the strong sense of opposition (logical complements, or negations) and the less strong sense
of opposition (logical contraries). Two sets are logical complements of each other if
everything in the universe is a member of one or the other set and not both.
Pairs of sets such as “dogs” and “non-dogs” are logical complements, because
everything in the universe is either a dog or it isn’t: “non-dogs” is the logical
complement of “dogs.” “Good” and “non-good” are opposites in the strong sense;
but “good” and “evil” are not opposites in the strong sense. If God follows the rules
of logic, he is bound to create non-good things if he creates good things.
But non-good things are not necessarily evil. “Good” and “evil” are contraries,
meaning that if X is one, X can’t be the other, but X might be in neither.
Contraries are the less rigid opposites exemplified in pairs like “Republican” and “Democrat”:
if one is a Republican, one isn’t a Democrat, and vice-versa, but one could also be
neither a Republican nor a Democrat (one could be a Libertarian or a Green, for example).
In the same way, because “good” and “evil” are contraries, a good thing
can’t be evil, an evil thing can’t be good, AND there are things that are
neither evil nor good, i.e., neutral things. If God follows the rules of logic
when he creates, then, he doesn’t have to create evil if he creates good.
If there is more than one thing, then everything that exists is either red or non-red
(members of one or the other complementary set); but this does not rule out the possibility
that everything that exists is red. Everything being red is perfectly consistent with the
claim that everything is either red or non-red. In the same way, if “good” and “non-good”
are opposites in the strong sense, then if there’s more than one thing, everything has to be
either “good” or “non-good”, which implies that it’s possible for everything to be good.
In other words, a God committed to the laws of logic does not violate the laws of logic if he makes everything good.
Finally, believers often give solution #2 to explain how we learn the difference between
good and evil. And solution #2 probably is a good description of how we often learn.
We learn what’s good by contrast with the bad. If everything seemed to be good all
the time, maybe we’d never be able to tell the difference between good and evil.
But even if that’s true, that doesn’t explain why evil and suffering must exist.
If God’s purpose in creating or allowing evil is simply pedagogical (to teach us
the difference), then surely he could think of a way to give us the lesson without
tormenting us in the process. If he can’t, he’s not omnipotent (unorthodox solution #1).
Furthermore, even if evil did have to exist for us to learn about it – and it’s not
clear why this should be so if God is omnipotent – then why so much evil?
It seems we could learn what’s bad without suffering quite so much. However,
God allows some people to suffer quite horribly and protractedly – much
more than enough for them to learn the lesson. This seems to show God’s just
not very nice (unorthodox solution #2).
Orthodox solution 3 comes in two common forms: one aesthetic, one moral.
The aesthetic version is summed up in Alexander Pope’s Essay on Man (1733): “All nature
is but art, unknown to thee; / All chance, direction, which thou canst not see; / All
discord, harmony not understood; / All partial evil, universal good.” What seems
like chance to us is really God’s intentionally-created work of the highest art;
what seems like discord or evil to us is really part of God’s bigger plan. The
universe really is as good as it can be from God’s point of view. Just as sometimes
discord adds to the beauty of a piece of music, so does “evil” (from the human point
of view) add to the greater awesomeness of God’s creation.
The moral version (often called “soul-making theodicy” and
associated with the 2nd-century bishop Irenaeus) says the universe is actually
better with some evil in it than it would be if there were none, because evil
gives us the opportunity to grow and develop morally and spiritually as a result
of our confronting it in faith. For example, if you get an opportunity to give
charity to a suffering person, then someone must be suffering in order to be
the recipient of your charity. If you yourself suffer, your suffering provides
an opportunity for you or someone else to grow morally and spiritually. Human
suffering simply must exist for people to grow morally and spiritually.
In either case, it’s just a matter of understanding God’s
priorities, a believer would say. In either case, God is not primarily concerned with
decreasing human suffering; God’s benevolence extends only so far. His ways are not
our ways. It is more important to God that the universe be as beautiful or awesome
as possible than that people suffer. It is more important to God that we be as
good as possible than that we be happy in this life, and in fact he’s set things
up so that we can reach our full spiritual potential only if we (or others)
suffer in this life. If you point out to a religious person that this scenario
makes God seem less than totally good (not to say sadistic), the religious
person might answer that we are happiest when we are most fully developed
morally and spiritually. (And this may be true, for those who reach the
apex of spiritual development.) But if you ask the religious person why God
set things up that way and not another – for surely, as Mackie points out,
an omnipotent God could have made human spiritual development possible without
suffering – the religious person says “I don’t know; His ways are not our ways.”
A “muscular Christian” might say “Suck it up.”
But it often rings hollow to suffering people when
believers tell them “God is good” or “God loves you.” For sufferers,
God often seems like the guard in a concentration camp; he doesn’t have
to torture you, but he does anyway, and then tells you, absurdly, that
he’s torturing you because he loves you. For Mackie, this so-called
orthodox “solution” masks unorthodox solution #2.
Orthodox solution #4 is often found in combination with orthodox
solution #3, as follows: God wants humans to develop morally and spiritually,
and free agency is necessary for that. From God’s point of view, the value of
human freedom (including the freedom to cause terrible suffering to other
humans) outweighs any suffering that this freedom causes. Some theologians,
e.g., John Hick, say that if humans didn’t suffer, humans would never be tested
and become better, so human goodness would be childlike or robotic.
Suffering must exist, then, to enable people to use their free will to “grow up”
morally and spiritually. This reduces to “His ways are not our ways”.
Mackie responds that God could have created humans
whose goodness was immutable; they freely choose only the good, and
become better and better, happier and happier. This is what happens to residents of heaven,
no? So why couldn’t God have made residents of earth the same way?
The response can only be “His ways are not our ways”.
And while that might be true, it is a solution that simply doesn’t
address the issues raised by the problem of evil.
Also, to many people, the free will response in
this form (“Grow up; suck it up; life is hard, etc.”) seems not to take
seriously the actual amount of suffering that many humans experience.
Even if some people develop morally from some suffering, it doesn’t follow
that anyone can develop morally from any amount of suffering. It seems
obvious that some people’s suffering is simply too much -- too great to
bear at all, let alone to develop morally as a result of it. Suffering
seems to kill some people before they have a chance to grow from it;
for example, a soldier with an excruciatingly painful bullet wound, or
person with terminal cancer, may die in agony, and as the infection or
disease progresses, the sufferers, as a matter of physiological fact,
become less and less capable of sustained thought. An observer who says “Look,
God is giving them a splendid opportunity for moral and spiritual growth, and
they’re just refusing to take it!” seems both cruel and ignorant of the
facts of biology.
Think of what Voldemort does to Longbottom’s parents in the
Harry Potter books. They don’t die, but they are destroyed nonetheless; as a
result of their torture by Voldemort, they become so incapacitated they are
unable to raise their son. Many people say the Nazi Holocaust is another good
example of sustained almost-unimaginable suffering; rather than calling forth
virtue in the victims, the Holocaust appeared to destroy many people both
psychologically and morally. Believers sometimes respond that no suffering
is unbearable, because God never gives people more suffering than they can
handle successfully. But that response again seems contrary to the facts of
biology: an injury capable of producing intense suffering, even if
it does not kill a person, can deprive a person of the capacity for sustained
sober reflection, e.g., cardiovascular accidents (strokes), or some forms of encephalitis.
It is often hard to see how the preservation of free
will can possibly be more worthwhile than the prevention of human suffering.
Try this thought experiment: Suppose you have the chance to prevent a gruesome
murder from happening, without incurring any harm to you, but you choose to
let the murder happen anyway. You could not use the free-will defense to justify
your inaction, could you? Seriously? Could you
argue that you were right not to prevent the murder, even if you were able
to, simply because you wanted to preserve the free-will of the murderer?
Yet this is supposedly God's reasoning. A God who values freedom more than human suffering seems just nasty (unorthodox solution 2). It’s no comfort to hear “His ways are not our ways” when he seems to act like a monster.
Orthodox view #4 takes a grim turn in Augustine.
I learned his views on free will and sin as a child in Catholic grammar school.
Augustine is particularly concerned with original sin. Augustine argues
that God created a perfect world without any evil or suffering.
Genesis 1:31: “God saw all that he had made and saw that it was very good.”
Augustine defined evil as the privation of goodness, just as blindness is
a privation of sight. Since evil is not an entity in itself, just like
blindness is not an entity in itself, God could not have created it.
Instead, evil (i.e., failure to attain the maximum good) originates from
free will possessed by angels and humans, who turned their back on God
and settled for a lesser form of goodness. As a result of Adam and Eve’s original sin,
the state of perfection was ruined by sin. Thus, all humans are worthy of
God’s punishment for Adam’s original sin because all humans are “seminally
present in the loins of Adam”. (This is why Jesus had to be born of a virgin
(no sperm involved) and also why Mary the mother of Jesus also had
to be “immaculately conceived” (no sperm involved in making her either)).
In Augustine's day, descendants of criminals were usually expected to
continue to suffer and pay for the crimes of their ancestors, so this
idea that blame for Adam's sin extends to all Adam's descendants would
not have been considered strange. In other words, because all humans
inherit Adam's blame, God permits Adam's descendants to suffer, because
he is a just God and we are worthy of punishment. (This is why it’s important
to be baptized; Baptism removes the original sin.) God chooses to offer
salvation to some people, but only he can choose who. There’s nothing we
can do to gain God’s grace if we’re not baptized. It follows from Augustine's
views that if Baptism is necessary for salvation, unbaptized babies and all
non-Catholics automatically go to hell. So in the Catholic Church anyone can
perform a Baptism. As a child raised in Catholic schools, I was also taught
that in an emergency, you don’t necessarily help save people or ease the
victims’ suffering: the first thing you do is baptize everyone in sight, just in case.
Mackie says the main reason to reject solution #4 is
the “incoherence” of the notion of free will. You may have learned about
this in your introductory philosophy classes. Most philosophers don’t agree with
Mackie that free will is incoherent, but most accept some form of determinism also.
It seems impossible to avoid determinism if God made an orderly universe in
which everything happens according to laws of nature, and God knows the future.
One common view among philosophers and theologians
is “soft determinism”: freedom consists in being able to do what you want
to do in the circumstances in which you find yourself.
A prisoner is not free to leave the prison, but is free to write to his mother.
However, according to soft determinism, we are not really free with respect to
our wants: we want what we want, according to our brain chemistry, our conditioning,
our nutritional state, and all the rest of the laws of the universe.
The universe is still determined. We are free in the sense that we can do
what we want; but the future is fixed nonetheless.
The indeterminist position on free will – the view that we
are free only if we can change the future by some non-physical power of our
minds alone – means even God can’t know what we’ll choose, and he can’t prevent
any of our free acts, i.e., the indeterminist position seems at odds with
both divine omniscience and omnipotence.
A lot of people say you are free to change your wants.
For example, if you find yourself wanting to crawl into a hole after a
bad breakup, you can, by an effort of will, force yourself to go out and
party, or talk to a counselor, etc., and thereby cheer yourself up, so you
no longer want to crawl into a hole. According to William James and others,
if you want to have faith in God, you can “will to believe”. If these
transformations are possible, though, according to soft determinism,
they are possible because of a physical substrate of preexisting brain conditions.
3 And you're likely not free with respect to those;
you don't control which genes you inherit, or your nutrition as a baby, nor the socio-economic position of your parents, and a whole host of other factors that affect your ability to change your mind and thereby change your brain.
So free will can't be the answer.
1. Some liberal Protestant theologians – pushing the
envelope of orthodoxy – actually favor unorthodox solution #1 (God is not
omnipotent). Omnipotence is not an essential attribute of God, they say. Unlimited omnipotence is incoherent anyway:
can God create a stone he can’t lift?
(If he can, he’s not omnipotent because he can’t lift it; if he can’t,
he’s not omnipotent, because he can’t create it.) Can God violate the laws of logic? Not a logos-type God,
they say. So don’t worry about God not
being omnipotent, they say; he’s still way more powerful than anything else. Back
2. One logical problem with qualified omnipotence is that God is also supposed to be immutable, i.e., unchanging, and it looks as though qualified omnipotence and immutability are contradictory attributes. Remember that God is supposed to be absolutely perfect (as Anselm says, the greatest conceivable being). If God could change, he would get better or maybe worse, but the point is, if he's absolutely perfect, he's already as good as he can be. There's no "better" where God is concerned. Now, think about qualified omnipotence. The key notion is that God chose to limit himself at some point; he chose not to interfere with the laws of nature or with human free will. But wouldn't that mean God thought about things, and decided it would be better if he changed his own attributes and behavior? Now, you could avoid the contradiction between qualified omnipotence and immutability if you're willing to deny immutability. Some theologians (e.g., process theologians) go this route, but process theologians' views are embraced primarily by educated, liberal Christians, and would be unthinkable for most. Another problem with qualified omnipotence is that the whole qualified-omnipotence story makes it sound like God is in time, which can't be quite right either. As Kant points out, we cannot possibly
understand what it would mean for a being in time not to change; but neither do we understand what it would
mean for a being to be "outside of time". In short, "qualified omnipotence" is tough to understand.
Back
3. Unless you believe in violations of the laws of nature, i.e., miracles. But the logos God made an orderly universe (and, if qualified omnipotence is correct, he stays out of it).
Hence, philosophers and theologians generally doubt that miracles (in the sense of
violations of the laws of nature) are really possible – one big difference
between the views of theologians and ordinary believers.
|